Analogy

Redundanz

The articles Analogism and Analogy (philosophy) overlap thematically. Information that you are looking for here may therefore also be found in the other article.
You are welcome to participate in the relevant redundancy discussion or to help directly to merge the articles or to better distinguish them from each other (→ instructions).

Analogism or analogical inference (Greek ἀναλογισμός analogismós) is an inference based on analogy between two objects according to the pattern:

A has similarity to B. B has property C. So A has property C too.

Objects can be beings, things or phenomena, the similarity can consist in other properties, symptoms, structures, relations and functions.

This method of inference is also called inference per analogiam (Latin ratiocinatio per analogiam). The conclusion by analogy is often granted probative value (which, however, is at best only conditionally given) and is then called proof by analogy.

Two basic types of analogy inference arise from the distinction between structural and functional analogy.

History

Antiquity to scholasticism

Analogism was already to be found as a paradeigma in Aristotle (in: first analytics). Theophrastus called this procedure of inference a conclusion from hypothetical premises. The Epicureans consider this procedure (o kata ten omoioteta tropos) as a means from appearances to the unknown. In Boethius this inference is called exemplum. In the theological doctrines of scholasticism the procedure acquires a special value for theological needs, especially with regard to positive statements about the divine conception according to the so-called analogy of being.

Analogies according to scholasticism

While David Hume counts analogy conclusions among the probability conclusions, Wilhelm Wundt classifies them among the subsumption conclusions (in: Logik I).

Approaches to the use of analogies in the general methodology of the natural sciences are first found in Francis Bacon and, in a more developed form, in John Stuart Mill.

Theory

Analogism is not, strictly speaking, a proof - it consists in inferring the uncertain parts of a not fully known system from knowledge of a similar but fully known one. It is therefore primarily an instrument for hypothesizing ­and has "only heuristic value".

The conclusion by analogy can only be a proof if the two systems, i.e. the mapping and the mapped system, are isomorphic to each other, at least in the corresponding subdomain for which the proof is given, and as long as the appropriate transformation rules are observed.

Conclusions by analogy proved to be extraordinarily fruitful and yielded important partial insights, until the realization of the quantization of energy and orbits in the case of atomic structures made the essential difference between the conditions of a solar system and the atomic structure apparent. This example shows at the same time the problem of analogism: it is a conclusion of probability. In the borderline case the analogy changes into isomorphism, the analogy, which at first is gained partially, i. e. starts from the agreement in some essential properties, structures etc., can be totalized by assigning corresponding elements. On the other hand, conclusions by analogy prove to be false if, apart from all similarity or agreement, an essential difference between the phenomena set in the analogy is demonstrable.

Questions and Answers

Q: What is an analogy?


A: An analogy is a comparison between two things that are similar in some way.

Q: Why do people draw analogies?


A: People draw analogies to make a concept easier to understand.

Q: What category of reasoning do analogies belong to?


A: Analogies belong to the category of inductive reasoning.

Q: Do the conclusions of analogies follow with certainty?


A: No, their conclusions do not follow with certainty but are only supported with varying degrees of strength.

Q: What is the difference between superficial and profound analogies?


A: Superficial analogies compare two things that might look alike but work quite differently, while profound analogies compare two things that might look different but work in ways like each other.

Q: What is the goal of finding profound analogies?


A: The goal of finding profound analogies is to teach us something worth knowing.

Q: How does Mario Bunge see analogy?


A: Mario Bunge sees analogy as a main way of getting new hypotheses which can be tested based on similarities in behaviour or structure.

AlegsaOnline.com - 2020 / 2023 - License CC3